In the original television series, The Lone Ranger rode through the Wild West with justice in his holster and truth on his tongue. Always by his side was Tonto—the reliable, courageous partner who never sought the spotlight. While the Lone Ranger galloped into danger, Tonto was his quiet strength, his cultural compass, his backup when the bullets ran out. It was a tale of friendship, loyalty, and a shared mission to clean the dirt off the frontier.But in the faraway land of Konoha, things aren’t quite the same.Here, the Lone Ranger rides alone—not because he’s a hero, but because Tonto refuses to get his boots dirty. The Lone Ranger battles corruption, disaster, and political bandits day and night, while Tonto’s main concern is curating his image on magical crystal screens, distributing skincare products with slogans like “Glow Up for Justice” and “Beauty Before Bureaucracy.”This Konoha Tonto isn’t interested in catching villains—he’s interested in catching votes. It’s no secret anymore. He’s already authored a glossy memoir titled "Tonto for the Next Lone Ranger", filled with vague metaphors, filtered photographs, and paragraphs that read more like influencer captions than political plans.Meanwhile, questions swirl like desert dust over Tonto’s origins. Where did he study? What did he learn? Does he even have a degree, or was it conjured in the same studio where his PR team edits his videos?Curiously, the same fog of uncertainty once shrouded the current President of Konoha, a man named Mulyono, whose diploma is as mysterious as his leadership style. And just like Mulyono, Tonto rides not on a horse of action, but on the algorithmic waves of social media fame and family endorsements.As 2029 approaches, Tonto no longer even hides his ambition. He waves, he winks, he whispers, “Continuity.” But the real question echoing in Konoha’s canyon is this:So, is it necessary to replace this fake Tonto with a real Tonto? Sure, because ... Can someone who’s never drawn a sword be trusted to lead the charge?In the intricate world of economic policy, there are few tasks more delicate than maintaining balance among three foundational objectives: stability, equality, and employment. These concerns are not theoretical luxuries—they are the bedrock of every modern economy, shaping how societies grow, distribute resources, and provide security for their people.
Stability can be addressed through macroeconomic tools such as the IS-LM model and business cycle theory, ensuring the economy avoids wild swings of boom and bust.Equality emerges in the discussion of income distribution and the classic trade-off between efficiency and fairness—highlighted in their chapter on “Efficiency versus Equality.”Employment is a core Keynesian concern, with considerable attention paid to unemployment, aggregate demand, and how government intervention can boost job creation.There's one more crucial issue: the environment. This topic fits neatly into the concept of market failure. Here’s an example: a factory generates pollution but doesn't pay for the damage it inflicts on our air and water. This creates an unfair and inefficient market. The government needs to step in to regulate this, perhaps through pollution taxes, emissions quotas, or even seemingly complex regulations that are vital for the planet's future.Now, you could argue that environmental issues link to stability (as environmental damage can destabilise the economy) and to equality (because it's often the less privileged who bear the brunt of the impact). However, it's generally best to discuss the environment as a distinct, increasingly central component of contemporary economic thought.So, while not formally labelled as such, these three pillars—stability, equality, and employment—form the backbone of the economic worldview. You could call it a silent trilogy.What is stability? When viewed from a political lens, stability refers to the endurance and legitimacy of a political system. It is marked by orderly transitions of power, effective governance, and institutions that command public trust. A politically stable country is not necessarily free of protest or disagreement, but it manages conflict through dialogue, law, and democratic processes rather than violence or authoritarian crackdowns. Political stability creates the foundation for consistent policymaking, which is crucial for both economic development and national cohesion.
In The Origins of Political Order: From Prehuman Times to the French Revolution, published in 2011 by Farrar, Straus and Giroux, Francis Fukuyama argues that the foundations of a politically stable state are not merely economic growth or military power, but rather the development of three key institutions: a strong and capable state, a system governed by the rule of law, and a mechanism for political accountability.A stable state, in Fukuyama’s view, is one where the state has authority to enforce order and deliver public goods, yet does not exercise power arbitrarily. The state must have institutional strength—it must be able to raise revenue, maintain bureaucracy, and ensure internal security—but that power must be constrained by laws that apply equally to rulers and citizens alike.Moreover, for long-term stability, elites must be held accountable. Political institutions should evolve to allow voices from broader society to influence power, preventing domination by narrow interest groups or dynastic rule. Fukuyama highlights how societies like China developed strong states early but lacked rule of law or accountability, leading to cycles of authoritarianism. In contrast, Europe's development was slower but resulted in a more balanced political order.Thus, stability is not about suppressing conflict, but about having the institutional capacity to manage conflict through legitimate, legal, and inclusive means. For Fukuyama, a truly stable political order is one that is simultaneously strong, lawful, and responsive—not merely efficient or forceful.In Political Order in Changing Societies (1968, Yale University Press), Samuel P. Huntington challenges the optimistic assumption that economic development automatically leads to political stability. For Huntington, stability is not defined by the absence of conflict, but by the capacity of political institutions to manage and absorb conflict in an orderly, institutionalised way.Huntington famously argues that political decay occurs when the rate of social mobilisation and economic change outpaces the development of political institutions. In other words, if a society is modernising quickly—people becoming more educated, urbanised, and politically aware—but its government institutions remain weak, rigid, or corrupt, then instability is almost inevitable. Revolutions, coups, and unrest are not caused by poverty alone, but by the frustration of rising expectations in a system that cannot adapt.He defines political stability not as a fixed state of peace, but as a balance between participation and institutionalisation. A society may have widespread political participation (like protests or electoral energy), but without strong institutions—such as effective parties, bureaucracies, and courts—it becomes vulnerable to chaos and demagoguery. Thus, for Huntington, stability requires not just inclusion but structure.Ultimately, Huntington sees political order as a product of institutions that are adaptable, legitimate, and strong enough to withstand pressure. Stability emerges not from suppressing dissent, but from having systems robust enough to handle it without collapse.From a social standpoint, stability is about the cohesion of society and the predictability of social life. It exists when individuals and groups feel secure in their rights, livelihoods, and identities. Social stability does not mean the absence of inequality or debate, but rather the presence of trust—trust that the system is not rigged, that justice is possible, and that tomorrow will not be worse simply because of one’s background. When this trust erodes, society risks fragmentation, populist extremism, and in extreme cases, civil unrest.
The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge, a seminal book published in 1966 by Anchor Books, authored by Peter L. Berger and Thomas Luckmann. W Berger and Luckmann argue that individuals internalise social norms and roles through daily interactions, which in turn leads to the institutionalisation of those norms. The repeated enactment of these roles makes societal patterns feel natural and unchangeable. As a result, stability is not a static given but an ongoing accomplishment—a fragile order upheld by human cooperation and mutual recognition. The book reveals that what we take for granted as “reality” is in fact a carefully constructed social edifice that supports stable societies.Berger and Luckmann redefine the concept of stability not as something imposed from above, but as something produced and maintained through everyday social interaction. They argue that human beings live in a world that is fundamentally created by shared meanings, roles, and routines. These shared frameworks are so deeply internalised that they become taken for granted, forming what they call a "social reality."Stability, in this framework, emerges when individuals repeatedly act out the same roles and expectations in a consistent environment. Over time, these routines become institutionalised, meaning they no longer require active negotiation. A teacher teaches, a judge judges, and a parent nurtures—not because they consciously invent these roles every morning, but because society has structured these expectations so deeply that they feel natural and inevitable.According to Berger and Luckmann, this social construction of reality is what gives societies a sense of order and predictability. Stability is, therefore, not something that exists on its own—it is the product of continuous collaboration, where people align their perceptions and actions with what others are doing. In this view, even large systems like religion, law, and education are human inventions that gain stability through repetition and shared belief.Thus, for Berger and Luckmann, social stability is not enforced—it is co-produced. It is the outcome of human beings constantly reaffirming the same scripts, expectations, and behaviours, until they seem like the only possible way to live.Robert K. Merton's Social Theory and Social Structure, originally published in 1949 by The Free Press, revolutionised sociology by introducing key concepts such as manifest and latent functions, middle-range theory, and social dysfunctions. When considering social stability, Merton’s idea of social systems working through manifest functions is essential: societies remain stable when institutions operate as intended, and when latent, unintended consequences do not overwhelm the system’s balance. Merton warned that dysfunctions—unexpected by-products of social arrangements—could loosen the cohesion that binds institutions and communities together. In essence, stability depends not only on formal rules and norms, but also on the subtle equilibrium among nuanced roles and structures that keep society functioning harmoniously.Merton introduced a groundbreaking way of thinking about how society functions. One of his most influential contributions is the distinction between manifest and latent functions. Manifest functions are the intended and explicitly recognised outcomes of a social activity or institution. For example, the manifest function of education is to transmit knowledge and prepare individuals for the workforce. Latent functions, on the other hand, are the unintended or hidden consequences of that same activity. In the case of education, a latent function might be the creation of social networks or even the reinforcement of class divisions.Merton also advanced the idea of middle-range theory, which was his response to what he saw as two extremes in sociological theory: abstract grand theorising (like Marxism or structural functionalism) and narrow empirical research without theoretical grounding. Middle-range theory sits in between. It offers frameworks that are not too broad to be vague, nor too narrow to be irrelevant—such as theories about deviance, role conflict, or bureaucracy. These are the kinds of theories that can be tested with data and applied in real-world settings.Another key concept Merton offered is that of social dysfunctions—the negative consequences of a social structure or institution. While many sociologists at the time assumed that all parts of society worked in harmony to preserve stability, Merton introduced a more nuanced view. He argued that not all aspects of social life are beneficial; some structures may cause harm, inequality, or instability. For instance, the criminal justice system may deter crime (a manifest function), but it might also disproportionately target marginalised communities (a dysfunction).Altogether, Merton’s concepts urge us to look beyond surface appearances. They remind us that what a system is supposed to do isn’t always what it actually does, and that society is a complex tangle of intended purposes and unintended effects.Foundations of Social Theory, published in 1990 by Belknap Press, James S. Coleman’s Foundations of Social Theory builds on rational-choice sociology to offer a rigorous account of how individual actions aggregate to systemic social structures. Coleman explains that social stability is achieved when institutions, norms, and networks align incentives so that self-interested individuals contribute to collective order—often through rational calculations rather than altruism. He illustrates how durable norms and shared expectations emerge organically when personal interests intersect with public goods. For Coleman, stability is less about coercion and more about institutionalised coordination, where individuals follow rules not because they must, but because it is in their rational interest to do so, thus weaving stable social fabrics from countless micro-level interactions.
Culturally, stability emerges when a shared sense of identity and continuity is preserved even amidst change. It involves the ability of a culture to evolve without losing its roots. Cultural stability does not mean stagnation or rigid traditionalism; rather, it allows a society to absorb new ideas while maintaining its core values. In multicultural societies, cultural stability requires mutual respect and space for diverse voices. Without it, cultural alienation and identity politics can undermine the collective fabric.
Eric Hobsbawm and Terence Ranger’s The Invention of Tradition (1983, Cambridge University Press) offers a compelling exploration of how cultural stability often depends on carefully crafted rituals and symbols that appear timeless but are, in fact, modern creations. They argue that many traditions are intentionally designed—such as royal ceremonies or patriotic customs—to create a palpable sense of continuity with the past. Despite their relatively recent origins, these invented traditions have become embedded in social consciousness through repetition and ritual.Hobsbawm and Ranger show that this process serves multiple purposes: it buttresses institutional authority, fosters group cohesion, and offers individuals a sense of belonging. By presenting these new traditions as ancient, societies establish a stable cultural framework that feels natural and enduring, even when it was newly constructed. The authors warn, however, that such manufactured stability can mask underlying social changes and anxieties—it sustains the status quo, but can also be inherently fragile, exposed when people begin to question or abandon those symbolic scripts.In essence, The Invention of Tradition teaches that cultural stability is often built on deliberate inventions that tie people to a shared past. It is not necessarily organic or age-old, but rather a social strategy that gives societies the illusion of permanence, even as they adapt to modern challenges.
In short, stability across these dimensions is not about freezing society in time. It’s about managing change without collapse—keeping the engine running, even as the landscape shifts. It is a dance between order and evolution, between heritage and progress. A stable nation is not a silent one—it is a society that speaks, adapts, and grows without tearing itself apart.
Economic stability refers to a condition in which an economy experiences low volatility in key indicators such as inflation, employment, exchange rates, and GDP growth. In other words, it describes a situation where shocks—whether political, financial, or external—do not severely disrupt the functioning of the economic system. Stability allows consumers, investors, and governments to make decisions with confidence, knowing that tomorrow will not look drastically different from today in terms of economic fundamentals.Economic growth theory is intimately linked with the idea of stability. Long-term, sustainable growth is only possible in a stable environment. Investment in infrastructure, education, and innovation—drivers of economic expansion—requires predictability and trust in future returns. This is why macroeconomic policies in growth models often assume a stable baseline: one cannot build skyscrapers on shaky ground. The Solow Growth Model, for instance, highlights the importance of steady capital accumulation and technological progress within a relatively stable framework.In capitalist economies, stability is both a goal and a constant challenge. Market economies thrive on competition and innovation, but they are also prone to cycles of boom and bust. Unregulated markets can lead to overheating or collapse, as seen in the 2008 financial crisis. Hence, even capitalist systems rely on regulatory institutions to moderate excess and maintain order. Central banks, for example, adjust interest rates to curb inflation or stimulate demand—tools that preserve the system’s overall health.Within liberal economic thought—especially classical and neoliberal traditions—economic stability is seen as a by-product of free markets operating without distortion. Liberal theorists argue that if markets are left alone, supply and demand will naturally balance out, promoting both efficiency and stability. However, critics have pointed out that unfettered liberalism often neglects social safety nets and systemic risks, leading to inequality and occasional instability.In The Illusion of Economic Stability (2004, Routledge), economist Eli Ginzberg provides a critical analysis of market self-regulation, arguing that the belief in natural economic equilibrium is fundamentally flawed. He demonstrates that capitalist economies are inherently prone to cyclical instability, driven not only by financial factors but also by technological changes, psychological behaviours, and sectoral power dynamics. Ginzberg contends that without active government intervention—through regulation, monetary policy, and fiscal measures—economic stability remains an illusion rather than a tangible state. He supports this perspective by examining patterns during the Great Depression and the decades that followed, showing how uncoordinated private sector actions led to deep downturns. In short, Ginzberg warns that stability in a capitalist system must be engineered, not assumed, requiring deliberate public policy to moderate market excesses and sustain growth.Eli Ginzberg titled his book The Illusion of Economic Stability as a deliberate provocation to challenge the dominant narrative that market economies, if left alone, will naturally regulate themselves into a state of balance. Through this title, Ginzberg critiques what he sees as an overly optimistic—and often dangerous—belief in the self-correcting powers of capitalism. He argues that the appearance of stability in modern economies is frequently misleading. Beneath the surface of apparent calm, there are deep structural vulnerabilities: income inequality, speculative financial bubbles, technological shocks, and policy blind spots.For Ginzberg, economic stability is not impossible, but it is not inherent to the capitalist system. Rather, it must be actively constructed and constantly maintained through robust governance, policy tools, and public institutions. In this view, the "illusion" lies not in the concept of stability itself, but in the assumption that markets alone can deliver it reliably and sustainably. By exposing this illusion, Ginzberg urges policymakers and economists to abandon complacency and embrace the responsibility of proactive economic stewardship.Thus, Ginzberg does not deny the possibility of economic stability; he questions the myth that stability is a natural by-product of free markets. His title is a caution: if we mistake temporary equilibrium for permanent health, we risk being blindsided by the next crisis.Economic stability refers to a condition in which an economy experiences steady growth, low inflation, manageable unemployment, and minimal fluctuations in key indicators like prices, investment, and production. In a stable economy, businesses can plan ahead, households feel confident about spending, and governments have more room to manage long-term policies without constantly reacting to crises. It provides a foundation for trust in markets, institutions, and national currencies.From a socialist perspective, economic stability is not merely about market balance but about equity, social protection, and collective well-being. Socialists argue that the capitalist pursuit of profit often leads to instability—through cycles of boom and bust, exploitative labour practices, and widening inequality. To achieve real stability, they propose stronger state regulation, public ownership of essential sectors, and policies that reduce disparities in wealth and access. Stability here is linked to social justice: a system is only stable when it provides security for all, not just the privileged few.In communist theory, particularly as framed by Karl Marx, the idea of economic stability in capitalism is viewed as illusory and temporary. Marx argued that capitalist systems are inherently unstable due to contradictions between labour and capital, which ultimately lead to crises. In communism, true stability can only be achieved when class divisions are abolished, private ownership of the means of production is eliminated, and economic planning replaces market anarchy. Under this system, economic activity is organised collectively to meet human needs rather than maximise profits, which is believed to ensure both fairness and long-term stability.Thus, while economic stability in liberal economics often focuses on maintaining market performance and investor confidence, socialist and communist traditions tie it directly to structural transformation—where the goal is not only smooth functioning but also justice, equality, and collective security.In essence, economic stability is the quiet engine room of modern economies. Without it, growth stumbles, capitalism self-destructs, and liberal dreams of efficiency unravel. Stability is not a passive condition; it must be actively protected through policy, regulation, and a recognition that markets, while powerful, are not infallible.Why does economic stability matter?